Transformation of Markers of the Deliberative Democracy Theory in Modern Political Science
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.31861/mediaforum.2022.10.25-42Keywords:
theory of democracy, deliberative democracy, deliberation, subjects of deliberation, forms of deliberation, consensusAbstract
The article studies the features of the transformation of markers of the theory of deliberative democracy in modern political science. It has been established that a feature of this model of democracy is the possibility of its definition as a process and form of politics aimed at transforming the individual interests of political subjects by organizing a rational discussion and reaching consensus on the problems that determine the subject field of political decisions. It is substantiated that the initial model of the theory of deliberative democracy by J. Bessett is based on the concept of institutionalized order, norms of public opinion and consensus, which are the source of the organization of the process of deliberation in a democratic political process. As one of the effective ways of making political decisions, deliberative democracy in the concept of J. Bessette functionally relies on discussion and discourse that form a space for competition of opinions and beliefs and public opinion in the status of resource support for the political course. In J. Bessette’s model of deliberative democracy, the status of the subject of discussion and discourse is assigned to politicians and experts and did not provide for the acquisition of such a status by all citizens.
It has been proved that modern versions of the theory of deliberative democracy, built around the idea of deliberation occurring with the participation of political institutions, civil society institutions and citizens, pay special attention to such markers as procedures, forms and results of deliberation. Meaning discussion, dialogue and discourse as forms of deliberation, delibe-rative democracy is modelled as a forum in which reasoning, ideas, opinions, preferences are transformed in the process of public discussion and approach rationality. According to the ideal model of deliberative democracy, political discussion (discourse, dialogue) should be oriented towards the development of a justified rational agreement on social norms. Only the result of a discussion in the form of consensus, reached in real actual political discourse, makes the social norm justified, substantiated and true. Achieving consensus in the deliberative model of democracy acts as a strategic skill based on intellectual and psychological techniques and technologies, the admissibility of which is derived from the procedures of the public political process and the virtues of political subjects. One such technique is the listening technique.
It is substantiated that discussions about the relationship between deliberation and legitimacy, which is reflected in the procedural principles of democracy (interaction and publicity; accountability; collective mind), have become an important direction in the transformation of markers of deliberative democracy. Democratic practices of relying on a deliberative model of legitimacy should take into account the vulnerability of political behaviour (participation, activity) to quasi-deliberative forms of organizing discussion and the conditional possibility of attaining consensus on the common good. Its search, not its achievement, is a resource of democracy that maintains interest and ensures inclusion in public problems that can be solved by means of politics.
Downloads
References
Ackerman, B., Fishkin J. 2004.Deliberation Day. New Haven; London.
Bächtiger, A, Parkinson, J. 2019. Mapping and Measuring Deliberation: Towards a New Deliberative Quality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Back, L.2007. The Art of Listening. Oxford; N. Y.: Berg Publishers.
Berlin, I. 2000. “Two Concepts of Liberty” in Berlin, I. The Proper Study of Mankind. N.Y.: Farrar, Straus and Giroux: 234–235.
Bessette, J. 1980.“Deliberative Democracy: The Majority Principle in Republican Government” in Howdemocratic is the Constitution? Washington, D.C.: AEI Press: 102–116.
Bessette, J.M. 1994. The Mild Voice of Reason: Deliberative Democracy and American National Government. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press.
Bessette, J. M., Pitney J. J. 2010. American Government and Politics: Deliberation, Democracy, and Citizenship. Boston, MA: Wadsworth.
Christiano, T. 2011. “The Significance of Public Deliberation. Deliberative Democracy”. Essays on Reason and Politics, 3:243–277.
Cohen, J. 1989. “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy”. Hablin, A., Pettit, B. (eds). The good polity. N.Y.: Blackwell: 67–92.
Coleman, S. A., Przybylska A., Sintomer Y. (eds.). 2015. Deliberation and Democracy: Innovative Processes and Institutions. New York: Peter Lang.
Dewey, J. 1954. The Public and its Problems. Chicago: Swallow Press.
Dobson, A. 2010.Democracy and Nature: Speaking and Listening // Political Studies. Vol. 58. Iss. 4. P. 762.
Elster, J. 1997. “The Market and the Forum” in Deliberative democracy: essays on reason and politics. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Ercan, S. A. 2019. “Deliberative Democracy: Taking Stock and Looking Ahead [Interview]”. Democratic Theory. 6 (1): 97–110.
Eriksen, E.O., Weigard, J. 2003. Understanding Habermas. Communicative Action and Deliberative Democracy. London.
Goodin, R. 2006.“Enfranchising the Earth, and its Alternatives”. Political Studies. 44(5):835-849.
Goodin, R. E. 2018. “If Deliberation is Everything, Maybe it’s Nothing” in Bächtiger, A., Dryzek, J. S, Mansbridge, J. (eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Deliberative Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 882–899.
Goodin, R. E., Niemeyer S. J. 2003. “When Does Deliberation Begin? Internal Reflection versus Public Discussion in Deliberative Democracy”. Political Studies. 51(4): 627–649.
Habermas, J. 1984. The Theory of Communicative Action. Vol. I. Boston: Beacon Press.
Habermas, J. 1996. Between Facts and Norms. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Habermas, J. 1998. Faktizität und Geltung: Beiträge zur Diskurstheorie des Rechts und des demokratischen Rechtsstaats. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.
Habermas, J. 2001. “Why Europe Needs a Constitution”. New Left Rev. 11:5–26.
Habermas, J. 2001.The Postnational Constellation: Political Essay. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Habermas, J. 2001a. “Constitutional Democracy: a Paradoxical Union of Contradictory Principles?” Polit. Theory. 29(6):766–781.
Habermas, J. 1997. “Popular Sovereignty as Procedure” in Deliberative democracy: essays on reason and politics. Cambridge: MIT Press: 33–46.
Hardin, R.1999.“Deliberation: Methods, Not Theory” in Macedo S. (ed.). Deliberative Politics. Essays on Democracy and Disagreement. New York: Oxford University Press: 103–122.
Hendriks, C. M. 2009. “Deliberative Governance in the Context of Power”. Policy and Society. 28 (3): 173–184.
Hendriks, C. M. 2016. “Coupling Citizens and Elites in Deliberative Systems: The Role of Institutional Design”. European Journal of Political Research. 55 (1): 43–60.
Hooghe, M. 1999. “The Rebuke of Thersites: Deliberative Democracy under Conditions of Inequality” Acta Politica. 4:287–301.
Lakatos, I. 1970. “History of Science and its Rational Reconstructions”. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association: 91–136.https://www.jstor.org/stable/495757 (accessed April 11, 2022).
Jefferson, Th. 2013. Thomas Jefferson on Democracy. New York: Wildside Press.
Johansson, L. G. 2016. “Theories about the Development of Science” in Philosophy of Science for Scientists. Springer Undergraduate Texts in Philosophy. Springer: 103–121.
Lefor, K.1989. Democracy and Political Theory. Minnesota: MIT Press, 1989.
Lenaghan, J. 1999.“Involving the Public in Rationing Decisions. The Experience of Citizens Juries” Health Policy. 49(1–2): 45–61.
Lovbrand, E., Pielke, R., Beck, S. 2011. A Democracy Paradox in Studiesof Science and Technology. Science, Technology and Human Values. 36(4):474–496.
MacIntyre, A. 1999. Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues. Chicago; La Salle: Open Court.
Miller, D. 1992. “Deliberative Democracy and Social Choice”. Political Studies. 40 (1): 54–67.
Miller, D., Dryzek J. S., List C. 2003. “Social Choice Theory and Deliberative Democracy: A Reconciliation”. British Journal of Political Science. 33(1): 1–23.
Misak, Ch. 2000. Truth, Politics, Morality: Pragmatism and Deliberation. London: Routledge.
Mouffe, Ch. 2000. “Politics and Passions: The Stakes of Democracy”. Ethical Perspectives. 2/3: 146–150.
Nabatchi, T., Gastil, J., Weiksner, G. M., Leighninger, M. (eds.). 2012. Democracy in Motion: Evaluating the Practice and Impact of Deliberative Civic Engagement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Niemeyer, S. J. 2011. “The Emancipatory Effect of Deliberation: Empirical Lessons from Mini-Publics,” Politics & Society. 39 (1): 103–140.
Owen, D., Smith, G. 2015 “Survey Article: Deliberation, Democracy, and the Systemic Turn”. The Journal of Political Philosophy. 23(2): 213–234.
Parkinson, J., Mansbridge J. (eds.). 2012. Deliberative Systems: Deliberative Democracy at the Large Scale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rippe, K.-P. 2001.“Ethikkommissionen in der Deliberativen Demokratie” in Kettner, M. (hrsg.). Angewandte Ethik als Politikum. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp:140–164.
Sanders L. M. 1997. “Against Deliberation”. Political Theory. 25(3):349.
Sass, J., Dryzek J. S. 2004. “Deliberative Cultures”. Political Theory. 42(1):3–25.
Scudder M. F. 2021. “Deliberative Democracy, More than Deliberation”. Political Studies. 2021. https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/pdf/10.1177/00323217211032624 (accessed April 15, 2022).